By Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Russell |
My own view on
religion is that of Lucretius. I regard it as a disease born of fear and as a
source of untold misery to the human race. I cannot, however, deny that it has
made some contributions to civilization.
It helped in early days to fix the
calendar, and it caused Egyptian priests to chronicle eclipses with such care
that in time they became able to predict them. These two services I am prepared
to acknowledge, but I do not know of any others.
The
word religion is used nowadays in a very loose sense. Some people, under the
influence of extreme Protestantism, employ the word to denote any serious
personal convictions as to morals or the nature of the universe. This use of
the word is quite unhistorical. Religion is primarily a social phenomenon.
Churches
may owe their origin to teachers with strong individual convictions, but these
teachers have seldom had much influence upon the churches that they have
founded, whereas churches have had enormous influence upon the communities in
which they flourished.
To take the case that is of most interest to members of
Western civilization: the teaching of Christ, as it appears in the Gospels, has
had extraordinarily little to do with the ethics of Christians. The most
important thing about Christianity, from a social and historical point of view,
is not Christ but the church, and if we are to judge of Christianity as a
social force we must not go to the Gospels for our material.
Christ taught that
you should give your goods to the poor, that you should not fight, that you
should not go to church, and that you should not punish adultery. Neither
Catholics nor Protestants have shown any strong desire to follow His teaching
in any of these respects.
Some of the Franciscans, it is true, attempted to
teach the doctrine of apostolic poverty, but the Pope condemned them, and their
doctrine was declared heretical. Or, again, consider such a text as "Judge
not, that ye be not judged," and ask yourself what influence such a text
has had upon the Inquisition and the Ku Klux Klan.
What
is true of Christianity is equally true of Buddhism. The Buddha was amiable and
enlightened; on his deathbed he laughed at his disciples for supposing that he
was immortal. But the Buddhist priesthood -- as it exists, for example, in
Tibet -- has been obscurantist, tyrannous, and cruel in the highest degree.
There
is nothing accidental about this difference between a church and its founder.
As soon as absolute truth is supposed to be contained in the sayings of a
certain man, there is a body of experts to interpret his sayings, and these
experts infallibly acquire power, since they hold the key to truth. Like any
other privileged caste, they use their power for their own advantage.
They are,
however, in one respect worse than any other privileged caste, since it is
their business to expound an unchanging truth, revealed once for all in utter
perfection, so that they become necessarily opponents of all intellectual and
moral progress.
The church opposed Galileo and Darwin; in our own day it opposes
Freud. In the days of its greatest power it went further in its opposition to
the intellectual life. Pope Gregory the Great wrote to a certain bishop a
letter beginning: "A report has reached us which we cannot mention without
a blush, that thou expoundest grammar to certain friends."
The bishop was
compelled by pontifical authority to desist from this wicked labor, and
Latinity did not recover until the Renaissance. It is not only intellectually
but also morally that religion is pernicious. I mean by this that it teaches
ethical codes which are not conducive to human happiness.
When, a few years
ago, a plebiscite was taken in Germany as to whether the deposed royal houses
should still be allowed to enjoy their private property, the churches in
Germany officially stated that it would be contrary to the teaching of
Christianity to deprive them of it. The churches, as everyone knows, opposed
the abolition of slavery as long as they dared, and with a few well-advertised
exceptions they oppose at the present day every movement toward economic
justice. The Pope has officially condemned Socialism.
Christianity and Sex
The
worst feature of the Christian religion, however, is its attitude toward sex --
an attitude so morbid and so unnatural that it can be understood only when
taken in relation to the sickness of the civilized world at the time the Roman
Empire was decaying.
We sometimes hear talk to the effect that Christianity
improved the status of women. This is one of the grossest perversions of
history that it is possible to make. Women cannot enjoy a tolerable position in
society where it is considered of the utmost importance that they should not
infringe a very rigid moral code.
Monks have always regarded Woman primarily as
the temptress; they have thought of her mainly as the inspirer of impure lusts.
The teaching of the church has been, and still is, that virginity is best, but
that for those who find this impossible marriage is permissible. "It is
better to marry than to burn," as St. Paul puts it.
By making marriage
indissoluble, and by stamping out all knowledge of the ars amandi, the church
did what it could to secure that the only form of sex which it permitted should
involve very little pleasure and a great deal of pain. The opposition to birth
control has, in fact, the same motive: if a woman has a child a year until she
dies worn out, it is not to be supposed that she will derive much pleasure from
her married life; therefore birth control must be discouraged.
The
conception of Sin which is bound up with Christian ethics is one that does an
extraordinary amount of harm, since it affords people an outlet for their
sadism which they believe to be legitimate, and even noble.
Take, for example,
the question of the prevention of syphilis. It is known that, by precautions
taken in advance, the danger of contracting this disease can be made
negligible. Christians, however, object to the dissemination of knowledge of
this fact, since they hold it good that sinners should be punished. They hold
this so good that they are even willing that punishment should extend to the
wives and children of sinners. There are in the world at the present moment
many thousands of children suffering from congenital syphilis who would never
have been born but for the desire of Christians to see sinners punished. I
cannot understand how doctrines leading us to this fiendish cruelty can be
considered to have any good effects upon morals.
It
is not only in regard to sexual behaviour but also in regard to knowledge on
sex subjects that the attitude of Christians is dangerous to human welfare.
Every person who has taken the trouble to study the question in an unbiased
spirit knows that the artificial ignorance on sex subjects which orthodox
Christians attempt to enforce upon the young is extremely dangerous to mental
and physical health, and causes in those who pick up their knowledge by the way
of "improper" talk, as most children do, an attitude that sex is in
itself indecent and ridiculous.
I do not think there can be any defense for the
view that knowledge is ever undesirable. I should not put barriers in the way
of the acquisition of knowledge by anybody at any age. But in the particular
case of sex knowledge there are much weightier arguments in its favor than in
the case of most other knowledge.
A person is much less likely to act wisely
when he is ignorant than when he is instructed, and it is ridiculous to give
young people a sense of sin because they have a natural curiosity about an
important matter.
Every
boy is interested in trains. Suppose we told him that an interest in trains is
wicked; suppose we kept his eyes bandaged whenever he was in a train or on a
railway station; suppose we never allowed the word "train" to be
mentioned in his presence and preserved an impenetrable mystery as to the means
by which he is transported from one place to another. The result would not be
that he would cease to be interested in trains; on the contrary, he would
become more interested than ever but would have a morbid sense of sin, because
this interest had been represented to him as improper.
Every boy of active
intelligence could by this means be rendered in a greater or less degree
neurasthenic. This is precisely what is done in the matter of sex; but, as sex
is more interesting than trains, the results are worse.
Almost every adult in a
Christian community is more or less diseased nervously as a result of the taboo
on sex knowledge when he or she was young. And the sense of sin which is thus
artificially implanted is one of the causes of cruelty, timidity, and stupidity
in later life.
There is no rational ground of any sort or kind in keeping a
child ignorant of anything that he may wish to know, whether on sex or on any
other matter. And we shall never get a sane population until this fact is
recognized in early education, which is impossible so long as the churches are
able to control educational politics.
Leaving
these comparatively detailed objections on one side, it is clear that the
fundamental doctrines of Christianity demand a great deal of ethical perversion
before they can be accepted.
The world, we are told, was created by a God who
is both good and omnipotent. Before He created the world He foresaw all the
pain and misery that it would contain; He is therefore responsible for all of
it.
It is useless to argue that the pain in the world is due to sin. In the
first place, this is not true; it is not sin that causes rivers to overflow
their banks or volcanoes to erupt. But even if it were true, it would make no
difference. If I were going to beget a child knowing that the child was going
to be a homicidal maniac, I should be responsible for his crimes. If God knew
in advance the sins of which man would be guilty, He was clearly responsible
for all the consequences of those sins when He decided to create man.
The usual
Christian argument is that the suffering in the world is a purification for sin
and is therefore a good thing. This argument is, of course, only a
rationalization of sadism; but in any case it is a very poor argument. I would
invite any Christian to accompany me to the children's ward of a hospital, to
watch the suffering that is there being endured, and then to persist in the
assertion that those children are so morally abandoned as to deserve what they
are suffering.
In order to bring himself to say this, a man must destroy in
himself all feelings of mercy and compassion. He must, in short, make himself
as cruel as the God in whom he believes. No man who believes that all is for
the best in this suffering world can keep his ethical values unimpaired, since
he is always having to find excuses for pain and misery.
The Objections to Religion
The
objections to religion are of two sorts -- intellectual and moral. The
intellectual objection is that there is no reason to suppose any religion true;
the moral objection is that religious precepts date from a time when men were
more cruel than they are and therefore tend to perpetuate inhumanities which
the moral conscience of the age would otherwise outgrow.
To
take the intellectual objection first: there is a certain tendency in our
practical age to consider that it does not much matter whether religious
teaching is true or not, since the important question is whether it is useful.
One question cannot, however, well be decided without the other. If we believe
the Christian religion, our notions of what is good will be different from what
they will be if we do not believe it. Therefore, to Christians, the effects of
Christianity may seem good, while to unbelievers they may seem bad.
Moreover,
the attitude that one ought to believe such and such a proposition,
independently of the question whether there is evidence in its favor, is an
attitude which produces hostility to evidence and causes us to close our minds
to every fact that does not suit our prejudices.
A
certain kind of scientific candor is a very important quality, and it is one
which can hardly exist in a man who imagines that there are things which it is
his duty to believe. We cannot, therefore, really decide whether religion does
good without investigating the question whether religion is true.
To
Christians, Mohammedans, and Jews the most fundamental question involved in the
truth of religion is the existence of God. In the days when religion was still
triumphant the word "God" had a perfectly definite meaning; but as a
result of the onslaughts of the Rationalists the word has become paler and
paler, until it is difficult to see what people mean when they assert that they
believe in God.
Let us take, for purposes of argument, Matthew Arnold's
definition: "A power not ourselves that makes for righteousness."
Perhaps we might make this even more vague and ask ourselves whether we have
any evidence of purpose in this universe apart from the purposes of living
beings on the surface of this planet.
The
usual argument of religious people on this subject is roughly as follows:
"I and my friends are persons of amazing intelligence and virtue. It is
hardly conceivable that so much intelligence and virtue could have come about
by chance. There must, therefore, be someone at least as intelligent and
virtuous as we are who set the cosmic machinery in motion with a view to
producing Us."
I am sorry to say that I do not find this argument so
impressive as it is found by those who use it. The universe is large; yet, if
we are to believe Eddington, there are probably nowhere else in the universe
beings as intelligent as men.
If you consider the total amount of matter in the
world and compare it with the amount forming the bodies of intelligent beings,
you will see that the latter bears an almost infinitesimal proportion to the
former.
Consequently, even if it is enormously improbable that the laws of
chance will produce an organism capable of intelligence out of a casual
selection of atoms, it is nevertheless probable that there will be in the
universe that very small number of such organisms that we do in fact find.
Then
again, considered as the climax to such a vast process, we do not really seem
to me sufficiently marvelous. Of course, I am aware that many divines are far
more marvelous than I am, and that I cannot wholly appreciate merits so far
transcending my own.
Nevertheless, even after making allowances under this
head, I cannot but think that Omnipotence operating through all eternity might
have produced something better. And then we have to reflect that even this
result is only a flash in the pan.
The earth will not always remain habitable;
the human race will die out, and if the cosmic process is to justify itself
hereafter it will have to do so elsewhere than on the surface of our planet..
And even if this should occur, it must stop sooner or later. The second law of
thermodynamics makes it scarcely possible to doubt that the universe is running
down, and that ultimately nothing of the slightest interest will be possible
anywhere. Of course, it is open to us to say that when that time comes God will
wind up the machinery again; but if we do not say this, we can base our
assertion only upon faith, not upon one shred of scientific evidence.
So far as
scientific evidence goes, the universe has crawled by slow stages to a somewhat
pitiful result on this earth and is going to crawl by still more pitiful stages
to a condition of universal death.
If this is to be taken as evidence of a
purpose, I can only say that the purpose is one that does not appeal to me. I
see no reason, therefore, to believe in any sort of God, however vague and
however attenuated. I leave on one side the old metaphysical arguments, since religious
apologists themselves have thrown them over.
The Soul and Immortality
The
Christian emphasis on the individual soul has had a profound influence upon the
ethics of Christian communities. It is a doctrine fundamentally akin to that of
the Stoics, arising as theirs did in communities that could no longer cherish
political hopes.
The natural impulse of the vigorous person of decent character
is to attempt to do good, but if he is deprived of all political power and of
all opportunity to influence events, he will be deflected from his natural
course and will decide that the important thing is to be good.
This is what
happened to the early Christians; it led to a conception of personal holiness
as something quite independent of beneficient action, since holiness had to be
something that could be achieved by people who were impotent in action. Social
virtue came therefore to be excluded from Christian ethics.
To this day
conventional Christians think an adulterer more wicked than a politician who
takes bribes, although the latter probably does a thousand times as much harm.
The medieval conception of virtue, as one sees in their pictures, was of
something wishy-washy, feeble, and sentimental.
The most virtuous man was the
man who retired from the world; the only men of action who were regarded as
saints were those who wasted the lives and substance of their subjects in
fighting the Turks, like St. Louis.
The church would never regard a man as a
saint because he reformed the finances, or the criminal law, or the judiciary.
Such mere contributions to human welfare would be regarded as of no importance.
I do not believe there is a single saint in the whole calendar whose saintship
is due to work of public utility.
With this separation between the social and the
moral person there went an increasing separation between soul and body, which
has survived in Christian metaphysics and in the systems derived from
Descartes.
One may say, broadly speaking, that the body represents the social
and public part of a man, whereas the soul represents the private part. In
emphasizing the soul, Christian ethics has made itself completely
individualistic. I think it is clear that the net result of all the centuries
of Christianity has been to make men more egotistic, more shut up in
themselves, than nature made them; for the impulses that naturally take a man
outside the walls of his ego are those of sex, parenthood, and patriotism or
herd instinct.
Sex the church did everything it could to decry and degrade;
family affection was decried by Christ himself and the bulk of his followers;
and patriotism could find no place among the subject populations of the Roman
Empire.
The polemic against the family in the Gospels is a matter that has not
received the attention it deserves. The church treats the Mother of Christ with
reverence, but He Himself showed little of this attitude. "Woman, what
have I to do with thee?" (John ii, 4) is His way of speaking to her. He
says also that He has come to set a man at variance against his father, the
daughter against her mother, and the daughter-in-law against her mother-in-law,
and that he that loveth father and mother more than Him is not worthy of Him
(Matt. x, 35-37).
All this means the breakup of the biological family tie for
the sake of creed -- an attitude which had a great deal to do with the
intolerance that came into the world with the spread of Christianity.
This
individualism culminated in the doctrine of the immortality of the individual
soul, which was to enjoy hereafter endless bliss or endless woe according to
circumstances. The circumstances upon which this momentous difference depended
were somewhat curious.
For example, if you died immediately after a priest had
sprinkled water upon you while pronouncing certain words, you inherited eternal
bliss; whereas, if after a long and virtuous life you happened to be struck by
lightning at a moment when you were using bad language because you had broken a
bootlace, you would inherit eternal torment.
I do not say that the modern
Protestant Christian believes this, nor even perhaps the modern Catholic
Christian who has not been adequately instructed in theology; but I do say that
this is the orthodox doctrine and was firmly believed until recent times. The
Spaniards in Mexico and Peru used to baptize Indian infants and then
immediately dash their brains out: by this means they secured that these
infants went to Heaven.
No orthodox Christian can find any logical reason for
condemning their action, although all nowadays do so. In countless ways the doctrine
of personal immortality in its Christian form has had disastrous effects upon
morals, and the metaphysical separation of soul and body has had disastrous
effects upon philosophy.
Sources of Intolerance
The
intolerance that spread over the world with the advent of Christianity is one
of the most curious features, due, I think, to the Jewish belief in
righteousness and in the exclusive reality of the Jewish God.
Why the Jews
should have had these peculiarities I do not know. They seem to have developed
during the captivity as a reaction against the attempt to absorb the Jews into
alien populations. However that may be, the Jews, and more especially the
prophets, invented emphasis upon personal righteousness and the idea that it is
wicked to tolerate any religion except one.
These two ideas have had an
extraordinarily disastrous effect upon Occidental history. The church made much
of the persecution of Christians by the Roman State before the time of
Constantine.
This persecution, however, was slight and intermittent and wholly
political. At all times, from the age of Constantine to the end of the
seventeenth century, Christians were far more fiercely persecuted by other
Christians than they ever were by the Roman emperors.
Before the rise of Christianity
this persecuting attitude was unknown to the ancient world except among the
Jews. If you read, for example, Herodotus, you find a bland and tolerant
account of the habits of the foreign nations he visited. Sometimes, it is true,
a peculiarly barbarous custom may shock him, but in general he is hospitable to
foreign gods and foreign customs. He is not anxious to prove that people who
call Zeus by some other name will suffer eternal punishment and ought to be put
to death in order that their punishment may begin as soon as possible.
This
attitude has been reserved for Christians. It is true that the modern Christian
is less robust, but that is not thanks to Christianity; it is thanks to the
generations of freethinkers, who from the Renaissance to the present day, have
made Christians ashamed of many of their traditional beliefs.
It is amusing to
hear the modern Christian telling you how mild and rationalistic Christianity
really is and ignoring the fact that all its mildness and rationalism is due to
the teaching of men who in their own day were persecuted by all orthodox
Christians.
Nobody nowadays believes that the world was created in 4004 b.c.;
but not so very long ago skepticism on this point was thought an abominable
crime. My great-great-grandfather, after observing the depth of the lava on the
slopes of Etna, came to the conclusion that the world must be older than the
orthodox supposed and published this opinion in a book. For this offense he was
cut by the county and ostracized from society. Had he been a man in humbler
circumstances, his punishment would doubtless have been more severe.
It is no
credit to the orthodox that they do not now believe all the absurdities that
were believed 150 years ago. The gradual emasculation of the Christian doctrine
has been effected in spite of the most vigorous resistance, and solely as the
result of the onslaughts of freethinkers.
The Doctrine of Free Will
The
attitude of the Christians on the subject of natural law has been curiously
vacillating and uncertain. There was, on the one hand, the doctrine of free
will, in which the great majority of Christians believed; and this doctrine
required that the acts of human beings at least should not be subject to
natural law.
There was, on the other hand, especially in the eighteenth and
nineteenth centuries, a belief in God as the Lawgiver and in natural law as one
of the main evidences of the existence of a Creator.
In recent times the
objection to the reign of law in the interests of free will has begun to be
felt more strongly than the belief in natural law as affording evidence for a
Lawgiver. Materialists used the laws of physics to show, or attempt to show,
that the movements of human bodies are mechanically determined, and that
consequently everything that we say and every change of position that we effect
fall outside the sphere of any possible free will.
If this be so, whatever may
be left for our unfettered volitions is of little value. If, when a man writes
a poem or commits a murder, the bodily movements involved in his act result
solely from physical causes, it would seem absurd to put up a statue to him in
the one case and to hang him in the other.
There might in certain metaphysical
systems remain a region of pure thought in which the will would be free; but,
since that can be communicated to others only by means of bodily movement, the
realm of freedom would be one that could never be the subject of communication
and could never have any social importance.
Then,
again, evolution has had a considerable influence upon those Christians who
have accepted it. They have seen that it will not do to make claims on behalf
of man which are totally different from those which are made on behalf of other
forms of life.
Therefore, in order to safeguard free will in man, they have
objected to every attempt at explaining the behaviour of living matter in terms
of physical and chemical laws. The position of Descartes, to the effect that
all lower animals are automata, no longer finds favor with liberal theologians.
The doctrine of continuity makes them inclined to go a step further still and
maintain that even what is called dead matter is not rigidly governed in its
behaviour by unalterable laws. They seem to have overlooked the fact that, if
you abolish the reign of law, you also abolish the possibility of miracles,
since miracles are acts of God which contravene the laws governing ordinary
phenomena.
I can, however, imagine the modern liberal theologian maintaining
with an air of profundity that all creation is miraculous, so that he no longer
needs to fasten upon certain occurrences as special evidence of Divine
intervention.
Under
the influence of this reaction against natural law, some Christian apologists
have seized upon the latest doctrines of the atom, which tend to show that the
physical laws in which we have hitherto believed have only an approximate and
average truth as applied to large numbers of atoms, while the individual
electron behaves pretty much as it likes.
My own belief is that this is a
temporary phase, and that the physicists will in time discover laws governing
minute phenomena, although these laws may differ considerably from those of
traditional physics.
However that may be, it is worth while to observe that the
modern doctrines as to minute phenomena have no bearing upon anything that is
of practical importance. Visible motions, and indeed all motions that make any
difference to anybody, involve such large numbers of atoms that they come well
within the scope of the old laws.
To write a poem or commit a murder (reverting
to our previous illustration), it is necessary to move an appreciable mass of
ink or lead. The electrons composing the ink may be dancing freely around their
little ballroom, but the ballroom as a whole is moving according to the old laws
of physics, and this alone is what concerns the poet and his publisher. The
modern doctrines, therefore, have no appreciable bearing upon any of those
problems of human interest with which the theologian is concerned.
The
free-will question consequently remains just where it was. Whatever may be
thought about it as a matter of ultimate metaphysics, it is quite clear that
nobody believes it in practice.
Everyone has always believed that it is
possible to train character; everyone has always known that alcohol or opium
will have a certain effect on behaviour. The apostle of free will maintains
that a man can by will power avoid getting drunk, but he does not maintain that
when drunk a man can say "British Constitution" as clearly as if he
were sober. And everybody who has ever had to do with children knows that a
suitable diet does more to make them virtuous than the most eloquent preaching
in the world.
The one effect that the free-will doctrine has in practice is to
prevent people from following out such common-sense knowledge to its rational
conclusion. When a man acts in ways that annoy us we wish to think him wicked,
and we refuse to face the fact that his annoying behaviour is a result of
antecedent causes which, if you follow them long enough, will take you beyond
the moment of his birth and therefore to events for which he cannot be held
responsible by any stretch of imagination.
No
man treats a motorcar as foolishly as he treats another human being. When the
car will not go, he does not attribute its annoying behaviour to sin; he does
not say, "You are a wicked motorcar, and I shall not give you any more
petrol until you go." He attempts to find out what is wrong and to set it
right. An analogous way of treating human beings is, however, considered to be
contrary to the truths of our holy religion. And this applies even in the
treatment of little children. Many children have bad habits which are
perpetuated by punishment but will probably pass away of themselves if left
unnoticed.
Nevertheless, nurses, with very few exceptions, consider it right to
inflict punishment, although by so doing they run the risk of causing insanity.
When insanity has been caused it is cited in courts of law as a proof of the
harmfulness of the habit, not of the punishment. (I am alluding to a recent
prosecution for obscenity in the State of New York.)
Reforms
in education have come very largely through the study of the insane and
feeble-minded, because they have not been held morally responsible for their
failures and have therefore been treated more scientifically than normal
children.
Until very recently it was held that, if a boy could not learn his
lesson, the proper cure was caning or flogging. This view is nearly extinct in
the treatment of children, but it survives in the criminal law. It is evident
that a man with a propensity to crime must be stopped, but so must a man who
has hydrophobia and wants to bite people, although nobody considers him morally
responsible. A man who is suffering from plague has to be imprisoned until he
is cured, although nobody thinks him wicked. The same thing should be done with
a man who suffers from a propensity to commit forgery; but there should be no
more idea of guilt in the one case than in the other. And this is only common
sense, though it is a form of common sense to which Christian ethics and
metaphysics are opposed.
To
judge of the moral influence of any institution upon a community, we have to
consider the kind of impulse which is embodied in the institution and the
degree to which the institution increases the efficacy of the impulse in that
community.
Sometimes the impulse concerned is quite obvious, sometimes it is
more hidden. An Alpine club, for example, obviously embodies the impulse to
adventure, and a learned society embodies the impulse toward knowledge.
The
family as an institution embodies jealousy and parental feeling; a football
club or a political party embodies the impulse toward competitive play; but the
two greatest social institutions -- namely, the church and the state -- are
more complex in their psychological motivation.
The primary purpose of the
state is clearly security against both internal criminals and external enemies.
It is rooted in the tendency of children to huddle together when they are
frightened and to look for a grown-up person who will give them a sense of
security.The church has more complex origins. Undoubtedly the most important
source of religion is fear; this can be seen in the present day, since anything
that causes alarm is apt to turn people's thoughts to God.
Battle, pestilence,
and shipwreck all tend to make people religious. Religion has, however, other
appeals besides that of terror; it appeals specifically to our human
self-esteem. If Christianity is true, mankind are not such pitiful worms as
they seem to be; they are of interest to the Creator of the universe, who takes
the trouble to be pleased with them when they behave well and displeased when
they behave badly.
This is a great compliment. We should not think of studying
an ants' nest to find out which of the ants performed their formicular duty,
and we should certainly not think of picking out those individual ants who were
remiss and putting them into a bonfire.
If God does this for us, it is a
compliment to our importance; and it is even a pleasanter compliment if he
awards to the good among us everlasting happiness in heaven. Then there is the
comparitively modern idea that cosmic evolution is all designed to bring about
the sort of results which we call good -- that is to say, the sort of results
that give us pleasure. Here again it is flattering to suppose that the universe
is controlled by a Being who shares our tastes and prejudices.
The Idea of Righteousness
The
third psychological impulse which is embodied in religion is that which has led
to the conception of righteousness. I am aware that many freethinkers treat
this conception with great respect and hold that it should be preserved in
spite of the decay of dogmatic religion. I cannot agree with them on this
point.
The psychological analysis of the idea of righteousness seems to me to
show that it is rooted in undesirable passions and ought not to be strengthened
by the imprimatur of reason.
Righteousness and unrighteousness must be taken
together; it is impossible to stress the one without stressing the other also.
Now, what is "unrighteousness" in practise? It is in practise
behaviour of a kind disliked by the herd.
By calling it unrighteousness, and by
arranging an elaborate system of ethics around this conception, the herd
justifies itself in wreaking punishment upon the objects of its own dislike,
while at the same time, since the herd is righteous by definition, it enhances
its own self-esteem at the very moment when it lets loose its impulse to
cruelty.
This is the psychology of lynching, and of the other ways in which
criminals are punished. The essence of the conception of righteousness,
therefore, is to afford an outlet for sadism by cloaking cruelty as justice.
But,
it will be said, the account you have been giving of righteousness is wholly
inapplicable to the Hebrew prophets, who, after all, on your own showing,
invented the idea. There is truth in this: righteousness in the mouths of the
Hebrew prophets meant what was approved by them and Yahweh.
One finds the same
attitude expressed in the Acts of the Apostles, where the Apostles began a
pronouncement with the words "For it seemed good to the Holy Ghost, and to
us" (Acts xv, 28). This kind of individual certainty as to God's tastes
and opinions cannot, however, be made the basis of any institution.
That has
always been the difficulty with which Protestantism has had to contend: a new
prophet could maintain that his revelation was more authentic than those of his
predecessors, and there was nothing in the general outlook of Protestantism to
show that this claim was invalid.
Consequently Protestantism split into
innumerable sects, which weakened one another; and there is reason to suppose
that a hundred years hence Catholicism will be the only effective representation
of the Christian faith.
In the Catholic Church inspiration such as the prophets
enjoyed has its place; but it is recognized that phenomena which look rather
like genuine divine inspiration may be inspired by the Devil, and it is the
business of the church to discriminate, just as it is the business of the art
connoisseur to know a genuine Leonardo from a forgery.
In this way revelation
becomes institutionalized at the same time. Righteousness is what the church
approves, and unrighteousness is what it disapproves. Thus the effective part
of the conception of righteousness is a justification of herd antipathy.
It
would seem, therefore, that the three human impulses embodied in religion are
fear, conceit, and hatred. The purpose of religion, one may say, is to give an
air of respectability to these passions, provided they run in certain channels.
It is because these passions make, on the whole, for human misery that religion
is a force for evil, since it permits men to indulge these passions without restraint,
where but for its sanction they might, at least to a certain degree, control
them.
I
can imagine at this point an objection, not likely to be urged perhaps by most
orthodox believers but nevertheless worthy to be examined. Hatred and fear, it
may be said, are essential human characteristics; mankind always has felt them
and always will. The best that you can do with them, I may be told, is to
direct them into certain channels in which they are less harmful than they
would be in certain other channels.
A Christian theologian might say that their
treatment by the church in analogous to its treatment of the sex impulse, which
it deplores. It attempts to render concupiscence innocuous by confining it
within the bounds of matrimony.
So, it may be said, if mankind must inevitably
feel hatred, it is better to direct this hatred against those who are really
harmful, and this is precisely what the church does by its conception of
righteousness.
To
this contention there are two replies -- one comparatively superficial; the
other going to the root of the matter. The superficial reply is that the
church's conception of righteousness is not the best possible; the fundamental
reply is that hatred and fear can, with our present psychological knowledge and
our present industrial technique, be eliminated altogether from human life.
To
take the first point first. The church's conception of righteousness is
socially undesirable in various ways -- first and foremost in its depriciation
of intelligence and science.
This defect is inherited from the Gospels. Christ
tells us to become as little children, but little children cannot understand
the differential calculus, or the principles of currency, or the modern methods
of combating disease.
To acquire such knowledge is no part of our duty,
according to the church. The church no longer contends that knowledge is in
itself sinful, though it did so in its palmy days; but the acquisition of
knowledge, even though not sinful, is dangerous, since it may lead to a pride
of intellect, and hence to a questioning of the Christian dogma.
Take, for
example, two men, one of whom has stamped out yellow fever throughout some
large region in the tropics but has in the course of his labors had occasional
relations with women to whom he was not married; while the other has been lazy
and shiftless, begetting a child a year until his wife died of exhaustion and
taking so little care of his children that half of them died from preventable
causes, but never indulging in illicit sexual intercourse.
Every good Christian
must maintain that the second of these men is more virtuous than the first.
Such an attitude is, of course, superstitious and totally contrary to reason.
Yet something of this absurdity is inevitable so long as avoidance of sin is thought
more important than positive merit, and so long as the importance of knowledge
as a help to a useful life is not recognized.
The
second and more fundamental objection to the utilization of fear and hatred
practised by the church is that these emotions can now be almost wholly
eliminated from human nature by educational, economic, and political reforms.
The educational reforms must be the basis, since men who feel hatred and fear
will also admire these emotions and wish to perpetuate them, although this
admiration and wish will probably be unconscious, as it is in the ordinary
Christian.
An education designed to eliminate fear is by no means difficult to
create. It is only necessary to treat a child with kindness, to put him in an
environment where initiative is possible without disastrous results, and to
save him from contact with adults who have irrational terrors, whether of the
dark, of mice, or of social revolution.
A child must also not be subject to
severe punishment, or to threats, or to grave and excessive reproof. To save a
child from hatred is a somewhat more elaborate business. Situations arousing
jealousy must be very carefully avoided by means of scrupulous and exact
justice as between different children.
A child must feel himself the object of
warm affection on the part of some at least of the adults with whom he has to
do, and he must not be thwarted in his natural activities and curiosities
except when danger to life or health is concerned.
In particular, there must be
no taboo on sex knowledge, or on conversation about matters which conventional
people consider improper. If these simple precepts are observed from the start,
the child will be fearless and friendly.
On
entering adult life, however, a young person so educated will find himself or
herself plunged into a world full of injustice, full of cruelty, full of
preventable misery.
The injustice, the cruelty, and the misery that exist in
the modern world are an inheritance from the past, and their ultimate source is
economic, since life-and-death competition for the means of subsistence was in
former days inevitable.
It is not inevitable in our age. With our present
industrial technique we can, if we choose, provide a tolerable subsistence for
everybody. We could also secure that the world's population should be
stationary if we were not prevented by the political influence of churches
which prefer war, pestilence, and famine to contraception.
The knowledge exists
by which universal happiness can be secured; the chief obstacle to its
utilization for that purpose is the teaching of religion.
Religion prevents our
children from having a rational education; religion prevents us from removing
the fundamental causes of war; religion prevents us from teaching the ethic of
scientific co-operation in place of the old fierce doctrines of sin and
punishment.
It is possible that mankind is on the threshold of a golden age;
but, if so, it will be necessary first to slay the dragon that guards the door,
and this dragon is religion.
No comments:
Post a Comment